Mary Astell’s writing reveals the existence of a remarkable modern feminism before the liberal feminism we term the first wave that celebrates the free-born woman on equal terms with the freeborn man. The Christian Religion, As professed by a Daughter of the Church of England (1705), Astell’s greatest work, proclaims an ascetic feminism that decries the liberal pieties and the concomitant commitment to such rights as life, liberty, and happiness—all correlates of worldly estate or property. Astell allows us to reinvestigate the valences of each term of the newly holy trinity to see how difficult it must have been for a thinking and religious modern woman of her time to endorse what no one could then know would become the predominant model for modern freedom. Some may hesitate to call Astell a feminist, but no other term will suffice for one who so strongly voiced her objections to customary rights that debased the equality of women and who so strongly affirmed a vision in which women were the equals of men in their ability to rise above the narrow constraints of property in defining the principle values of human life.
I. The intellectual context: Norris and Astell, Locke and Masham
Mary Astell (1666-1731), daughter of a Newcastle coal merchant, is celebrated by George Ballard as the “great ornament of her sex and country” in his pioneering early study of female authors,
Though widely recognized as her major work, Mary Astell’s
Much more sober and restrained in tone than in the
Women are not invested with any great authority on earth, but they have God-given reason that makes them more than equal spiritual counterparts of men. Women are at an advantage in this realm because they are not encumbered by worldly property:
This passage demonstrates how different Astell’s thinking is on the subject of private property from Locke’s. Astell does not endorse unlimited personal wealth, but strongly supports “a secret and cheerful distribution of our Goods to our Necessitous Neighbour, for GOD’s sake, and with no other prospect but of a Reward from Him” (
Locke’s famous definition of individual property as life, liberty, and estate appears in Chapter 7 of the
For Locke, the proper function of a political society is to guarantee the preservation of private property. The freedom of each individual in the state of nature is given up to the community that establishes and enforces the laws that guarantee and preserve the property of each man who is bound together in civil society by a common obligation to uphold the political compact. Where such a compact, punishable by death, does not hold, man remains in the “perfect
Astell’s
Astell’s High Church Tory stance remains strongly wary of such latitudinous open-mindedness as a dangerous form of ungodliness. Astell herself was accused by contemporaries of harboring a suspiciously papist investment in the monastic life upon the publication of her first work,
Little is known about Mary Astell’s own education, but it is widely assumed that she must have been influenced by her uncle, the clergyman Ralph Astell, who had been educated at Cambridge in the 1650s and was directly under Lady Masham’s father, Ralph Cudworth, at Emmanuel in 1653. Karen O’Brien remarks that, “[t]he clash between Cambridge Platonist and Lockean ideas formed one of the main axes of theological debate in the early eighteenth century” (36). The divide between Cartesians and materialists in the period also tended to overlap with the division between Tory and Whig politics. Springborg notes that “if English materialists from the late Hobbes on tended to be Whiggish, the Cartesians tended to be Tory” (
The philosophical and political differences stem from the shifting definition of reason itself in the period. The older Cartesian model of the philosophical system as “starting from a highest being and from a highest, intuitively grasped certainty,” rigorously traced through proof and inference to piece together the whole chain of possible knowledge, was ceding to the “model and pattern of contemporary natural science” (Cassirer 6). “The status of Reason was well and truly up for grabs in the 1690s,” writes theological historian Sara Apatrei. Whereas the Cambridge Platonists viewed Reason as an innate divine faculty of the human mind, strongly anchored in revealed truth, the “Socinians disputed core Christian doctrines on the basis of their congruency with Reason and plain Scripture: most notoriously Christ’s divinity and pre-existence, and the Trinity” (97). The new scientific and philosophical ideas of the seventeenth century promoted an empirical approach to religion, whereas the older rationalism, or
Astell’s faith in Reason must be understood within this theological tradition. She could not sympathize with the scientific rationalism of the anti-Trinitarians who were abandoning revealed religion, yet she also wished to maintain a moderate distance from the enthusiastic sects. Non-conformists presented a greater danger for her than latitudinarians. Both Platonic rationalism and the more “modern” rationalism that sought truth in evidence strove to keep at arm’s distance the radical pessimism of Calvinism of the more radical sects.
Astell’s Platonism is evident right from the opening manifesto in which she declares that “Reason is that light which GOD himself has set up in my mind to lead me to Him, I will therefore follow it so far as it can conduct me” (
Life, liberty, and estate, in Locke’s version--or life, liberty and
1Carol Pateman’s The Sexual Contract (1988) was seminal in this regard. Patricia Springborg’s modern editions of A Serious Proposal (2002) (hereafter cited as SR) and Political Writings (1996) (hereafter cited as PW), were followed by D. Derek Tayor and Melvyn New’s 2005 edition of Letters Concerning the Love of God, coauthored with John Norris. Springborg’s book-length study, Mary Astell: Theorist of Freedom from Domination (2005), and William Kolbrenner and Michal Michelson’s collection of critical essays, Mary Astell: Reason, Gender, Faith (2007), reflect the growing expansion of interest in Astell in the twenty-firstcentury. 2No modern edition existed until Jacqueline Broad’s 2013 edition was published by the Centre for Reformation and Renaissance Studies and ITER. All references to The Christian Religion in this article are to the 1717 edition with Appendix (London: printed by W. B. for R. Wilkin), made available through Gale ECCO Print Editions. All page references are to this edition, hereafter cited as CR. 3See Springborg, introductions to PW and SR and Goldie, “Mary Astell and John Locke.” 4In 1704 alone, Astell published Moderation Truly Stated: Or a Review of a Late Pamphlet entitul’d Moderation a Vertue, A Fair Way with the Dissenters and their Patrons, An Impartial Enquiry into the Causes of Rebellion and Civil War in this Kingdom. Her last published work was Bart’lemy Fair or an Enquiry after Wit in which due Respect is had to a Letter Concerning Enthusiasm republished in 1722 as An Enquiry after Wit wherein the Trifling Arguing and Impious Raillery of the Late Earl of Shaftesbury in his Letter Concerning Enthusiasm and Other Profane Writers are Fully Answered, and Justly Exposed. As this list shows, Astell was never afraid to address the major issues and to attack the most famous men of her times. 5Francis Atterbury, Bishop of Rochester, in a letter to Hoadley, complained that Astell was “a little offensive and shocking in her expressions.” Ballard who quotes from the letter writes, “But this I will venture to say in Mrs. Astell’s behalf; that I believe those who have perused her book of the Christian Religion and read with attention what she has there written upon decency and decorum (which was printed and published long before she had this conversation with the Bishop) will not very easily fall into his way of thinking” (387-88). 6The publication of this work drew Locke firmly into the ranks of deist Socinians like John Toland in the minds of his critics. Astell comments in the Appendix, added in the second edition (1717) to collate all the attacks on Locke, that “the Ladies Religion seems to be little else but an Abstract of the Reasonableness of Christianity, with all those disadvantages that usually attend Abridgments” (309). 7For Malebranche, all events either physical or mental, are merely “occasions” of the manifestation of God’s will. For a good overview, see the excellent introduction to the modern edition of Letters by E. Derek Taylor and Melvyn New, in particular 14-15. 8“An Englishman, as one to whom liberty is natural, may go to heaven in his own way,” Voltaire remarks in Letter 5 “On the Church of England” of Letters Concerning the English Nation (1726-8), 26. 9For an excellent overview of Natural Law theory, see Charles Taylor, A Secular Age: “God made man rational, and he made him sociable, and with an instinct to his own conservation. It is plain from this what norms he held binding on his creatures. Plainly they must respect each other’s life, liberty and estate. . . . The aim of Natural Law theory was to provide a rational terrain d’entente replacing not only the ex parte theories of extremist religious partisans, but later on, in its Lockean variant, also setting aside other, dangerously flawed reactions to the religious strife, such as theories of sovereignty unbound by any law” (126-27). 10Springborg (1998) provides an excellent summary of Masham’s critique. There is no modern edition of this work. 11See Springborg introduction to SP, in particular 14-15. 12See Ruth Perry’s “Mary Asell and the Feminist Critique of Possessive Individualism” for a good overview of Astell’s critique of Lockean liberalism. 13In Part Four of the Discourse on Method where he arrives at the famous Cogito, Descartes ties his certitude in the truth of his reason with his belief in the existence of a supreme and perfect God: “The very principle which I took as a rule to start with, namely, that all those things which we conceived very clearly and very distinctly are true, is known to be true only because God exists, and because he is a supreme and perfect Being, and because everything in us necessarily comes from him” (29).
II. Freedom, duty and the question of happiness
Early feminists were in a tough quandary when it came to the question of female liberty. Legally dispossessed, they fell, if not in the same category, a neighboring category to those who were prohibited from owning property because they were themselves chattel, namely slaves. Hence the frequent rhetorical invocation of slavery by women as in Mary Astell’s most-quoted moment in the 1706 Preface to
Astell gives short shrift to the so-called Masters who so naturally assume the “
The question that remains then is what freedom could have meant for Astell. Philip Pettit argues in
Freedom from a
Defined this way, Astell clearly believes in the moral freedom of any woman who bases her actions solely on her Reason without paying regard to custom or worldly standards. But this does not make her a de facto proto-republican. As Springborg explains, in Roman law, as in Natural Law theory, “the jurists’ concept of rights was still, despite the rhetoric, objective rather than subjective. . . . Deprived of the right to own property until the various married women’s property acts of the 1880s, European and transatlantic married women lacked Defined this way, Astell clearly believes in the moral freedom of any woman who bases her actions solely on her Reason without paying regard to custom or worldly standards. But this does not make her a de facto proto-republican. As Springborg explains, in Roman law, as in Natural Law theory, “the jurists’ concept of rights was still, despite the rhetoric, objective rather than subjective. . . . Deprived of the right to own property until the various married women’s property acts of the 1880s, European and transatlantic married women lacked legal personality because of the terms in which this was defined” (
Nonetheless, Astell’s forthrightness on the topic of liberty is such that she is described as a proto-Republican by Skinner and Pettit. Republican freedom posited as a moral freedom from domination, rather than a negative freedom conditioned by property and law, is identified as informing Astell’s impassioned “If all Men are born Free” cry cited above.16 However, just as Astell spurns the pieties of the Natural Law theorists, she equally scorns republicans in the mold of Milton: “how much soever Arbitrary Power may be dislik’d on a Throne, not Milton himself wou’d cry up Liberty to poor Female Slaves” (
Hilda Smith notes that women in Astell’s time relied heavily on Descartes because Cartesian rationalism “provided the crucial ingredient for these feminists’ proof of women’s essential equality and gave incentive to work for a society where women could employ their powers to the fullest to understand truth, both godly and secular” (6). Women and men were equal in Reason, and “a woman should follow the same path to salvation as a man” (Smith 119). The title of Astell’s work emphasizes that hers is the Christian religion of the Church of England. The emphasis on reason is one of the key characteristics of the Anglican Church as it distanced itself from the Calvinist doctrine of the Reformed Church that emphasized human depravity and the absolute power of grace to redeem fallen man through election. Astell’s rationalism thus stems not only from the Cartesian
Rivers describes the tension that arises between the competing “languages of reason and grace,” before the language of sentiment eventually overtakes both in the course of the eighteenth century. Too much emphasis on rationality leads to Socinianism. Latitudinarians sympathized with this approach and hence were frequently charged with Socinianism. Too little emphasis leads to enthusiasm and non-conformity, and so Astell is careful to tread the middle path of a spiritually endorsed reason that enables the human subject to fulfill her duty on earth.
To choose duty, or obedience to God’s law is the only freedom worthy of the true Christian for Astell. The Word of God is the only true law, the “Divine Law promulg’d to Mankind, to which GOD requires their obedience under the highest Penalties” (13-14). Astell realizes others may have different ideas about the role of reason and the meaning of liberty: “Whatever Doctrine or Precept tends to the humbling of our proud Understandings, the subduing of our stubborn Wills, and the restraining of our exorbitant Affections, (tho’ we may call these
Sections II, III, and IV are all devoted to the topic of Duty, first to God, then to our neighbors, and finally to ourselves. Duty is a major concern for all serious female writers in the English tradition, and Astell allows us to see that “duty” is the correlate of “freedom” and not its antithesis in Anglican thought. The influence of this theological development is crucial in defining the future of the English
A veteran of the pamphlet wars, Astell is no stranger to low attacks, especially when it comes to her favorite subject of derision, the state of nature of the contractarians. In her own version of the state of nature, all men are religious creatures born not free from God’s will, but with the desire to conform to that will. Those who do not fall into this model are “Monsters rather than Men.” The freewill choice to subject oneself to God’s will is the rational freedom that lies at the heart of Astell’s logic. Duty as the freedom to choose subjection is perhaps the most extreme example of a positive freedom. Here we can see how the peculiar combination of rationalism and freedom results in the strong emphasis on duty over grace in the Anglican psyche.
The final section on our duty to ourselves is by far the longest and reveals how wary Astell is of the liberal modern ideals of sociable and worldly conviviality. Astell’s conception of freedom follows the Pauline model, which celebrates freedom from the world, or death to the world—mortification—which renders any discussion of her understanding of freedom related to material possession moot. Endless happiness can only be achieved through endless mortification. Astell adopts the Pauline standard absolutely:
Lest her readers think that such deprivation be the inverse of happiness, she specifically emphasizes, “Nor is the subjecting of the Body to the Mind in reality a Pain, on the contrary it is a Pleasure, as being most agreeable to the Nature and Reason of things” (
Mortification may hardly seem a model for liberation, but the libratory potential of Pauline thought is explored by Giorgio Agamben in
The Pauline call to freedom/mortification is reiterated in Galatians 2:20: “I am crucified with Christ: nevertheless I live; yet not I, but Christ liveth in me: and the life which I now live in the flesh I live by the faith of the Son of God, who loved me, and gave himself for me.” To profess oneself a Christian is to claim a new identity forged through a new calling as slave to Christ.
Agamben’s second chapter explicates the meaning of
We can read Astell as fully participating in Paul’s messianic vision whereby we are “but one Body in Christ, and every one Members one of another.” Membership in the Church of Christ, or
In this new body of the church, or
Astell reserves her most serious accusation of Locke for last when she charges “the great man,” of perverting the Christian religion in
This is a major critique. The Trinity lies at the heart of the raging religious controversy in late seventeenth-century England as “the beleaguered Trinity came to symbolize the assault of a dangerously forensic rationalism on the transcendent and mystical aspects of Christian religion” (Apetrei 117). Overly literal rationalist interpretations are carried out at the expense of the “secret mysteries of a Divine Life, of a New Nature, of Christ formed in our hearts”22 in the words of Ralph Cudworth, leading Cambridge Platonist and father of Damaris Masham. The investment in a mystical Platonist illuminism curiously akin to the direct illumination of the Quakers within High Church theology continues into the eighteenth century in a certain strand of Tory pietism, especially under the influence of William Law, mentor to Samuel Johnson amongst others. This strand can be also linked backwards to the religious sensibility of Blaise Pascal, who refused to cede religion solely to theological rationalization. Jonathan Israel comments that Pascal presciently introduced to theology “what might be termed an anti-philosophical philosophy: ‘se moquer de la philosophie, c’est vraiment philosopher’” (
Astell condemns Locke’s
The finale of Astell’s work is a lengthy apostrophe to the Messiah, Son of God, whose death permits “the Comforter or
Astell’s work reveals the remarkable modern feminism before the liberal feminism we term the first wave that celebrates the free-born woman on equal terms with the free-born man. Some may hesitate to call Astell a feminist, but no other term will suffice for one who so strongly voiced her objections to customary rights that debased the equality of women and who so strongly affirmed a vision in which women were the equals of men in their ability to rise above the narrow constraints of property. Rachel Weil observes that Astell’s “political universe is divided between two kinds of people, the egotistical and the pious: the former try to control the world in accordance with their own desires, the latter restrain their impulses in accordance with their duty” (146). Contemptuous of liberal male claims for freedom from tyranny, Astell strongly denounced their hypocritical and selfish desire to “engross this World.”
Ultimately, Astell can be read in the context of the larger battle between the Ancients and the Moderns. “To be modern is to be self-liberating and self-making, and thus not merely to be in a history or tradition but to make history,” according to Michael Allen Gillespie. The first
14Reprinted in Springborg Ed. Political Writings. Hereafter cited as RM. 15The key Berlin text on liberty is “Two Concepts of Liberty,” first presented as the Inaugural Lectural for the Chichele chair of Social and Political Theory at Oxford in 1958. 16“Mary Astell’s rhetorical intentions in making this remark are complex and difficult to discern, but the very fact that the passage is so often quoted testifies to the appeal of non-domination as a feminist ideal” (Pettit 139). 17Springborg notes that Royalists “understood republicanism to be a species of heresy. And they immediately saw how academic—and how hollow—the freedom-slavery argument really was in the seventeenth century, a time at which Britain was active in the slave trade abroad and in which indentured servitude annulled the freedom of many at home” (Astell 211) and that “strategies like the melding of Whig purposes to the grand strategies of the Roman Republic—which indulged in just such rhetorical strategies in the name of an aggrandizing oligarchy itself--were not lost on Mary Astell, herself an adept at the rhetoric of the Grub Street gutter press” (Astell 236). 18These nonjurors who included such prominent figures as William Sancroft, Archbishop of Canterbury, viewed the events of 1688 as invasion rather than “glorious” revolution, the Whig version of events that has survived along with the winning side’s story. Although they did not agree with the policies of James II, in particular his attempts to re-establish Catholicism, and were sympathetic to intervention by the Protestant William, nonjurors drew the line at William’s assuming the throne. 19“Immemorial Prescription is on their side in these parts of the World, Antient Tradition and Modern Usage! Our Fathers have all along both Taught and Practis’d Superiority over the weaker Sex, and consequently Women are by Nature inferior to Men” (RM 29). See Choi (2010) and (2011) for closer discussion. 20“This is a modest endeavor, but it depends on a preliminary wager: we will be treating this first verse as though its first ten words recapitulate the meaning of the text in its entirety” (6). 21“Even though modern philologists doubt this etymology, what interests us is that it allows us to relate messianic klēsis to a key concept in Marxian thought. It has often been noted that Marx was the first to substitute the Gallicism Klasse for the more common Stand” (Agamben 29). 22From A Sermon Before the House of Commons (1647), as cited in Apetrei, 121. 23See Israel, Revolutionary Ideas. 24“For the Love of our Enemies is by no means consistent with that account of Love that is given by our great Men. . . . They tell us, that Love is nothing else but that disposition of Mind we find in our selves towards any thing we are pleasd’ with; and that without this Principle of Love to our Neighbour, we can’t discharge what we owe to him. . . . Now if we cannot Love but what we are pleas’d with, and that it is certain, for Reason, as well as the Experience of Mankind, assures us, that we cannot be pleas’d with our Enemies, consequently we cannot Love them” (CR 312.) The passages in italics are quotations from Masham’s Discourse of the Love of God, assumed by Astell to have been authored by Locke himself.