Numbers have been regarded as one-sided, and their exactly readings have been understood as the results of scalar implicature. This Neo-Gricean view on numbers becomes less persuasive due to theoretical and experimental counterarguments. In spite of growing evidence for their two- sided readings, numbers are still one-sided in modal sentences. Moreover, the occurrence of a negative operator may worsen the acceptability of modal sentences with numbers. In the framework of Vector Space Semantics, I have derived two-sided readings of numbers with the simple notions of monotonicity of modals and scopal relations between modals and numbers. I have also argued that the awkwardness incurred by negation is the result of a split set of vectors for a number. The incoherent set of vectors is understood as the lack of an ideal behavior, which is against the deontic modality of the sentence.
Traditionally, an interpretation domain consists of individuals (and possibly materials), and nouns and predicates are understood to denote sets of individuals (or materials) in this domain. Depending on theories, additional entities of events or situations are required to construe verbal predicates. No matter how diverse entities an interpretation domain includes, all these entities are defined by inclusion. A larger set includes smaller sets, which reflects relative specificity of meanings between expressions.
Unlike nouns and predicates, the interpretations of number words cannot be done by the set inclusion of entities. The meaning of
In the exactly reading, both the upper and lower bounds are specified by the number, so it is also called a ‘two-sided’ reading. In the at-least reading, only the lower bound is restricted by the number, which makes it called a ‘one-sided’ reading.
No matter which reading a number word takes, its interpretation is varied in a sentence with a modal operator.
In both (2a) and (2b),
To trace the interaction between number words and modal and negative operators, I will consider the interpretations of number words in semantic literature. Much theoretical and experimental evidence shows that numbers are uniformly interpreted as two-sided. Based on the exactly readings of numbers, I will critically review a previous analysis on number readings in sentences with operators, and propose an alternative analysis in the framework of Vector Space Semantics.
II. Interpretations of Numbers in Modal Sentences
2.1 Interpretations of Number Words
The semantics of cardinal number words has been considered as no different from other scalar quantifiers such as
This dominant view on numbers has been challenged with theoretical and experimental evidence in the last decade. In contrast with the lowerbounded semantics of numbers, this alternative view takes the ‘Exact Semantics’ on numbers, where the lexical meanings of numbers include both upper and lower bounds. Koenig (1991) argues that if we follow the Neo-Gricean analysis, the semantic role of numeral modifiers is not systematic. Numeral modifiers that are lower-bounded or two-sided, e.g., at
According to the Neo-Gricean analysis, numbers and scalar quantifiers are equally one-sidedand assigned exactly readings by scalar implicature. The exact interpretations of scalar quantifiers are explicitly represented by delimiting the upper bound. For example, the exact reading of
If numbers are only lower-bounded as Neo-Gricean theorists’ claim, the explicit representation of lower limit should not affect the truth of sentences with a number. Lexically specified lower limits affect only the pragmatics of sentences. However, as Nouwen (2010) notes, the acceptability of a sentence may be worsened with the addition of a numeral modifier delimiting a lower (or upper) limit.2
In the Neo-Gricean analysis, the propositional content of (3a) is that John registered at least three classes, and the exactly reading of
Another point made by Koenig (1991) is that the apparent scalar implicature of numbers is related with the distributivity of predicates. Implicature cancellation is allowed only for a number occurring with a distributive predicate but not for the one with a collective predicate.
The theoretical debate between the Neo-Gricean analysisand the Exact Semantics leads to a number of experimental study. (cf. Noveck 2001, Papafragou & Musolino 2003, Musolino 2004, Huang & Snedeker 2009, Geurts et al 2009) The experimental results of the study show that both children and adults take two-sided readings instead of lower-bounded ones. For example, Huang et al (2009) conducted an experiment to test whether number words have lower bound readings or exactly readings. The experiment is designed to provide contexts in which scalar implicatures are cancelled to disentangle semantic and pragmatic contributions to the meaning of number words. Since implicatures are not part of truthconditional content of sentences with a number word, they should be cancelled (or not calculated) in contexts in which none of given options are compatible with them. In the experiment, they provide three pictures, two with visible boxes and one with a covered box. One of the visible boxes contains one fish, and the other one has three fish.If the Neo-Gricean theory works with subjects’ interpretations of numbers, subjects are supposed to choose the box with three fish when asked ‘give me the box with two fish.’ Since none of the visible boxes matches with the request, subjects should cancel the scalar implicature and pick out the boxwith a larger number of fish than two. On the other hand, the Exact Semantics predicts that subjects should choose the covered box because there is no match for the request. When there was no exact match, 95% of children and 100% of the adults chose the covered box in the experiment. The experimental result is inconsistent with the Neo-Gricean analysis, showing that number words haveexact semantics from the very early stage of acquisition.
Since the exactly readings of numbers gain more support with theoretical and experimental evidence, I will assume that numbers have both upper and lower limits in the following discussion.
2.2 Interpretations of Sentences with Modals and Numbers
As discussed in the previous section, much evidence shows that number words are two-sided and have exactly readings. Part of the evidence is provided by Nouwen (2010), which points out the fact that numbers may not be modified by expressions with an upper or lower limit.
As shown by the awkwardness in (5b) and (5c), the numeral modifiers
The sentences in (6a) and (6b) are distinguished from (5a) only by the insertion of the modal operators
The semantic change of the number is not limited to
These sentences have different contexts with different operators, but they have the same bound readings. The sentences with the existential operators all have at-most readings while those with the universal operators have at-least readings. The consistent division of the interpretations suggests that the different bound readings of the numbers are due to the different monotonicity of the modal operators. Then, here is a question to be answered: why does the insertion of the modal operators change the numeral readings of the sentences? No matter which strategy is taken to account for the meaning change, it should be based on the interaction of the semantics of modal operators and numbers.
What affects the interpretations of numbers is not confined to modal operators but includes negative operators. When sentences are not accompanied by number words as in (9), the modal operators in the sentences trigger quantification over worlds.
The existential modal operator in (9a) induces the reading that there is a world w (compatible with your requirements) such that John meets Mary in w. The universal modal operator in (9b) makes it construed that for every world w (compatible with your requirements), John meets Mary in w. When a negative operator occurs in these sentences, it involves the negation of the existence or universality of such worlds. Hence, the two sentences in (10) have logically equal readings, and similarly those in (11) are judged to be equal.
The negation of the existence of the world where John meets Mary has the same logical effect of asserting that for every world w, John does not meet Mary in w. The same relation holds in the sentences in (11).
The paralleled readings in (10) and (11) are not maintained when they occur with a number word as in (12) and (13).
(12a) and (12b), the counterparts of (10a) and (10b), are acceptable, showing the same logical equivalence. However, (13a) and (13b) are not acceptable unlike the sentences in (11). Hence, another question related with semantics of numbers is why the occurrence of the negative operator feeds into an asymmetry in the acceptability of sentences.
1Geurts (2006) argues that number words are used in many different ways and provides a list of usages as follows: (i) a. arithmetical: Five is the fourth Fibonacci number. b. quantifying: Five ducks entered the lobby. c. predicative: These are five buckets. d. adjectival: the five girls e. measure: five pounds of buckwheat f. label: Chanel number five Based on this categorization, Geurts argues that the semantics of number words cannot be just one but specified differently depending on their actual use. In most literature, the quantifying role of numbers is mainly discussed, so other diverse uses of number are not in the scope of the current study. 2Nouwen (2010) notices that numeral modifiers representing maximality or minimality (e.g., at least/minimally and at most/ maximally) cannot occur with numerals having definite amount readings. In (3b), the number of classes that John registered is specifically determined before the utterance, and thus the modifier at least cannot modify three in the sentence. Nouwen accounts for the awkwardness with the notion of Gricean maxims. A definite amount for the number makes the application of the numeral modifier vacuous, which is against the maxim of brevity.
III. A Previous Analysis on Numbers in Modal Sentences
Many analyses on the semantics of numbers follow the Neo-Gricean view and assume that numbers are one-sided and have at least readings. Their exactly readings are due to the result of the application of the quantity maxim. Since the Neo-Gricean view is regarded as dominant, the semantics of numbers is discussed in the same way as scalar quantifiers, scalar adjectives, or comparatives. As discussed in section 2.1, much theoretical and experimental evidence shows that numbers are semantically two-sided. Hence, it is not necessary to review previous analyses on numbers that are based on the Neo-Gricean view of numbers.
In contrast with most previous analyses, Kennedy (in progress) argues for the two-sided interpretations of numbers. When numbers occur without being accompanied by other operators, they are consistently construed as having exactly readings. However, occurring with other modal operators, numbers may be interpreted as one-sided. Kennedy argues that the one-sided readings of numbers are the results of the scopal interactions between numbers and modals. For instance,
To get the numeral interpretation of numbers, Kennedy makes use of the operator
In the wide scope reading of the modal in (15b), the sentence is construed that in every world w that is accessible to the contextually given w0, the maximal number of documents that applicants submit in w is four. The maximal number of documents is restricted to four in all the worlds, so the exactly reading of the number is derived. In contrast, the wide scope reading of the number in (15), each world may have different numbers of documents, and the max operator yields the maximal number that all the worlds share. Hence, this corresponds to the lower bound reading of the number. According to Kennedy, although numbers are lexically two-sided, their upper or lower bound readings may be derived by the scopal interaction with modals.
In Kennedy’s analysis, numbers may have one-sided readings,and which side is bounded is determined by the monotonicity of modal operators they occur with. Since the monotonicity of modal operators is not changeable, minimal and maximal readings of numbers should not be affected by contexts. Although numbers usually have upper bound readings occurring with an Ï operator and lower bound readings occurring with an Å operator, they may have reversed readings depending on contexts.
According to the real world knowledge, buying more books is usually harder to be permitted due to the cost for the books. This makes the minimal reading of
Just like the sentences in (16), a more prominent reading of (17) is the maximal reading of
This is a restriction on the maximal speed for John’s driving. In addition to this maximal reading, a less prominent reading of
The contrasted acceptability shown in (12) and (13) is not discussed by Kennedy. However, given the role of modal monotonicity, it is not easy to imagine an account to be incorporated in his analysis.
IV. An Alternative Analysis in Vector Space Semantics
To provide a theoretical framework for the interpretations of scalar expressions, Zwartz (1997) and Zwartz & Winter (2000) develop ‘Vector Space Semantics (VSS).’ ‘Vectors,’ newly introduced primitives, are directed line segments in space. With certain operations, vectors form a vector space
Vectors are subject to algebraic functions such as addition, subtraction, and multiplication as defined in (18). Any two vectors
To see how the algebraic functions work for vectors, we will consider the following vector space.
Two vectors
Zwartz & Winter (2000) argue that vectors are properly used to represent spatial relations between objects. The interpretation of a locative preposition like
The relative position is represented by a pair of vectors like <
Winter (2005) shows how vectors may be properly used to represent adjective interpretations.First, Winter defines a scale, which consists of two elements: (i) a unit vector, i.e., a vector of norm 1, which determines the dimension measured by an adjective and (ii) a set of real numbers that specify the legitimate values along this dimension. A context determines how large a unit vector is, and a scale defined by a unit vector is discrete. To incorporate a contextual value for a scalar reading, a standard value is postulated. The interpretation of a scalar adjective like
Any vector that is greater than -3 in the downward scale or less than 3 in the upward scale is included in the interpretation of short. Then, anyone who is shorter than 3 by unit vector, or 3 feet, is considered short.
4.2 One-sided Readings of Numbers in Modal Sentences
In this section, I discuss in the framework of VSS how numbers are assigned one-sided readings occurring with modal operators. While number words are semantically two-side bound, their one-sided readings are attributed to the monotonicity of modal operators. The two-sided readings of numbers make it possible that either upward or downward scales are selected for their interpretations depending on contexts.
When a sentence does not encompass any degree expression, its interpretation is to assert the truth or the existence of the event that the sentence describes. For example, (23a) asserts the proposition that John drove or the existence of John’s driving event depending on theories.
When a number word occurs in a sentence as in (23b), the truth of the sentence is not checked only by the existence of John’s driving event but the event should meet a specific property of 60km. To assert this event property, a scalar structure for speed is needed. As noted in section2.1, number words are two-sided and have exactly readings. This means that numbers themselves are not monotoneand that both upward and downward scalar structures are available for the interpretations of numbers.
For a given pair of antonymous scalar adjectives, the upward monotone adjective is unmarked. For example, the scalar adjectives
(24a) is a proposition that John drives at the speed of 60 km. Since John’s driving is measured by kilometer, the unit vector
In contrast with the two-sided reading of (24a), 60 km in (25a) is bound only in its upper limit as paraphrased in (25b).
When the existential modal operator takes wide scope over the number, (25a) is construed that it is possible that John drives 60 km. In ordinary contexts, the monotone reading of the sentence is that the upper limit of John’s driving is 60 km. As discussed above, numbers themselves are not monotone, and thus both upward and downward scales are available for the interpretations. However, the unmarked scale is upward if there is no contextual requirement for the opposite. Hence, (25a) is construed in the upward speed scale, which is represented in (26a).
Since
Along with the unmarked interpretation in (26b), (25a) may also have a marked reading. Suppose that driving slowly is problematic and harder to be permitted, e.g., the German autoban. In this situation, how slowly people drive is a main concern, and (27a) is more properly construed like the paraphrase in (27b).
Since slow driving is a problem, what is allowed in (27a) is the lower speed limit. This marked interpretation is legitimately represented in a downward scale as in (28a).
When there is no upper limit for speed, the scale is from the infinity to zero. On the other hand, if the context has a high speed limit
Numerals are understood as taking scope. This implies that the number word may take wide scope over the modal operator. A third reading for (29a) is the wide scope reading of
Note that the monotone reading of the number is due to the monotonicity of the operator. When the number takes wide scope, it is not affected by the operator. Then,
When a number word occurs with the universal modal as in (30a), it is interpreted in the same way except that the number is upward monotone. The unmarked reading of (30a) is the lower bound reading of
In the unmarked reading, how fast people drive is a main concern according to the real world knowledge. Thus, the speed required to people in every ideal world is the lower limit. On the other hand, when driving slowly makes a problem, the requirement for people in every ideal world is the upper limit. Just like the sentence with the existential modal, the unmarked reading of (30a) is construed in the upward scale as in (31a) whereas the marked one is interpreted in the downward scale as in (31b).
What is different from (26a) and (28a) is that the vectors in (31a) and (31b) are upward monotone due to the upward monotonicity of the operator. Hence, in the unmarked reading of (31a), all the vectors that are greater than<0, 60ㆍ
(32a) says that for every world w that is accessible to the contextually given world w0, John drives at the speed of 60 km or higher. When the context provides a contextual value
4.3 The Semantics of Negated Modal Sentences
When a sentence does not include any monotone expression, the occurrence of a negative operator plays the role of negating the proposition. However, in a sentence with one, it has the effect of negating the monotonicity.
Occurring with a scalar expression, a negative operator reverses the direction of its scale. According to Zwarts & Winter (2000), antonymous scalar predicates are mapped into reversed directions of scales in VSS as shown by the contrast of
Given the roles of a negative operator, dual changes are incurred in sentences accompanied by both a modal and a scalar expression. One is to negate the modal assertion and the other is to reverse the direction of the scalar expression. For example, when
Just as
The focus of negation in (36) is not on the event of driving but on the speed. John can still drive but not at the speed of 60 km. Hence, what is negated is the vectors entailed by the positive counterpart sentence
The scale in (37a) is upward and
(38) says that there is no world w that is accessible to the contextually given world w0 such that John drives in w at the speed of d, which is less than 60 km in the downward scale. To put it in the upward scale, (38) is logically similar to say that John is not allowed to drive greater than 60 km. This is a prohibition on driving fast. Hence, the negation in (36) provides a clear requirement for the ideal behavior for John.
As noted in section 2.2, when a universal modal occurs in a negated sentence, it is not as natural as an existential modal.
In the most prominent reading,
When the negation in (39) applies to this divided set of vectors, it should have an effect similar to the proposition that John is not required to drive less than 60 km and greater than 100 km. Technically speaking, there is no scalar structure to include this split set of vectors because of their different monotonicity. A more serious problem is that there is no consistent requirement of ideal behavior for John. It is not clear that what is prohibited on John’s driving between driving slowly or driving fast. The awkwardness of (39) is attributed to this incoherent prohibition on John, which is represented by the divided set of vectors.
We have discussed the unmarked readings of (36) and (39). As noted in section 4.2, these sentences may be interpreted in the marked situation, which is based on the reversed direction of a scale. The change of the scalar direction yields a complementary set of vectors. Then, the negation of the existential sentence in (36) is interpreted with a divided set of vectors while that of the universal sentence in (39) is construed with a coherent set of vectors. The acceptability judgment of the sentences will be also the opposite from the ones in the unmarked case. Since the primary reading is derived in the unmarked situation, the overall judgment is that (36) sounds more acceptable than (39). However, when a context gears strongly for the marked case, the judgment for the sentences will be different.Part of the reason that (39) is not completely unacceptable but just quite awkward is due to the existence of this secondary reading.
4.4 The Semantics of Negated Predicates under a Modal Scope
When a sentence is accompanied by a number word, the negation of this sentence focuses on the degree or amount of the number denotation.
A sentence without a number in (41a) involves the negation of the proposition that John drove or the denial of the existence of the event of John’s driving itself. However, when the sentence is followed by the number word as in (41b), the focus of negation does not lie on the event but on the degree of the number.7 As discussed in Kwak (2010), when the negative operator applies to the number in VSS, what is negated is not the whole numeral value of 60 km but the excess or the shortage between 60 km and the actual speed of John’s driving.8 Suppose that John actually drove 55km. Then, the negation of (41b) asserts that the excess of 5 km is not true with the actual driving. On the other hand, if John drove 65 km, the negation asserts the shortage of 5 km from the actual speed is not true. Hence, the concept of standard value
The formal representation in (42a) says that there is a set of worlds w in which John did not drive at the speed from t0 and 60 km. Since the negation is about the excess or shortage value from the standard value, i.e., the actual speed of John’s driving, the negated reading of (41b) is ambiguous depending on the relative locality of the negated value and the standard value. This ambiguity of the negated sentence is instantiated by the selection of a scalar structure. If the standard value is lower than the negated value, then an upward scale is selected for the interpretation. For example, when the actual speed is 55 km, t0 is 55 and the located vector is <55ㆍ
When negative predicates occur in the scope of modality as in (43a), it is assigned the unmarked interpretation in (43b) or the marked one in (43c).
According to (43b), when the standard value
In contrast with the clear requirement for the ideal behavior for John in (43), the modal reading in (44a) is not straightforward.
Since (44a) is different from (43a) only by the modal operator, the formal interpretation in (44b) is identical to (43b) except for the modality. In this unmarked reading, the standard value is lower than the negated numeral. Say that the standard value or the ideal speed is 59 km. Since
In addition to the readings discussed above, (43a) and (44a) have the inversed scope readings in which the negative operator takes scope over the modal operators. In this inversed relation, the negative operator does not negate the speed of
3The minus number in the downward scale does not mean that the degree has a minus value. For instance, -3 with the unit vector of foot does not refer to -3 feet. The minus number shows that the degree moves in a downward scale which starts from a large number and moves to a small number. This is why the degree in the downward scale may be reinterpreted in the upward scale in (22). 4The semantics of tense is not considered in this study for the simplicity of discussion. The variable w in (24) is over possible worlds while win deontic modal sentences is over ideal worlds. I do not distinguish these two types of variables in this study. 5When the vectors in the downward scale are reinterpreted in the upward scale, the interpretation in (28b) is represented as follows. (i) ∃w∈Accwo[drivew(d)(j) ^ d ∈ {<0, tㆍus>: 60≤t (≤100/∞}] 6Vectors for short make a smaller set than those for not tall because the standard value for short is lower than that for tall. When shorter than 5 feet is understood as not tall, the criterion for short height is usually lower than 5 feet. Hence, although not tall and short are construed in the same downward height scale, their standard values are different. This distinction makes the meaning difference between not tall and short. 7Since both of the negative operator and the number take scope, (42) has another reading in which the number takes wide scope over the negative. This wide scope reading is paraphrased that 60 km is not the one that John drove. Note that numbers are two-sided and non-monotone. Hence, the wide scope reading of 60 km does not have entailments about speed. It is just a contrasted reading such that 60 km is not the correct speed that John drove but something else. 8This vector space interpretation of a negated number is useful to account for distinct entailments depending on the contextual value. See Kwak (2010) for more discussion. 9This is a revised interpretation of the negative degree sentence, which is proposed in Kwak (2011). Kwak (2010) suggests one differential reading, which is assumed to be instantiated on either an upward or downward scale. This is too vague and not guaranteed that the interpretation is always defined. Thus, Kwak (2011) proposes two differential reading of different monotonicity as in (42).
The semantics of number words was not paid much attention to because they were treated like other scalar quantifiers. They were considered to be one-sided and interpreted to have at-least readings. Their exactly readings, which are two-sided, were derived by scalar implicature. This Neo-Gricean view on numbers has been challenged by theoretical and experimental study over the past decade. The explicit specification of one-sided readings is not allowed for numbers occurring with expressions for a definite amount, and apparent scalar implicature is not possible with a distributive predicate. Experimental evidence also shows that both children and adults consistently take two-sided readings of numbers instead of cancelling scalar implicature.
In spite of the evidence for the two-sided readings of numbers, they appear to have one-sided readings occurring with modal operators. Numbers in the scope of an existential modal have at-most readings while those in the scope of a universal modal have at-least readings. Moreover, the occurrence of negative operator may worsen the acceptability of sentences with a modal and a number. Kennedy (in progress) suggests that the one-sided readings of numbers are the results of scopal interactions between numbers and modals. I have argued that the monotonicity of numbers may be reversed depending on contexts, and that these less prominent readings cannot be derived in Kennedy’s analysis.
To derive one-sided readings of numbers, I have discussed the semantics of modals and numbers in the framework of Vector Space Semantics (VSS). Scalar expressions are interpreted in directed scales in VSS, and upward or downward scales may be selected by the monotonicity of scalar expressions. I have suggested that numbers are affected by the monotonicity of modals although they are lexically two-sided. Numbers in the scope of an existential modal are downward monotone while those in the scope of a universal modal are upward monotone. Along with the monotonicity of numbers, I have argued that which direction of scale is taken for an interpretation may be affected by context. In an unmarked situation, an upward scale is adopted for the interpretation of a positive sentence. However, a downward scale may also be used in a marked situation. Two directional scales and the monotonicity of numbers in a modal scope provide an explanation for the different interpretations of numbers in modal sentences. Given the semantics of numbers, I haveshown that the insertion of a negative operator may incur a split set of vectors for a modal sentence with a number. The incoherent set of vectors is construed as the lack of an ideal behavior, which does not fit with the semantics of a deontic modal operator. With the basic notions of monotonicity and scope relations between modals, numbers, and negative operators, I have derived contextually affected interpretations of modal sentences with numbers and provided an account for the awkwardness incurred by the insertion of a negative operator.