검색 전체 메뉴
PDF
맨 위로
OA 학술지
Reconsideration of Event Structure in the Generative Lexicon
  • 비영리 CC BY-NC
ABSTRACT
Reconsideration of Event Structure in the Generative Lexicon
KEYWORD
event structure , lexical inference , lexical presupposition , lexical entailment , mereological
  • 1. Introduction

    Event structure, in the Generative Lexicon (hereafter, GL), is a representation level designed to capture lexical aspectual properties of event-denoting expressions. In this paper, I propose to extend event structure by incorporating lexically inferred subevents into event structure and representing inferential relations – presupposition and entailment – between an event and its proper subevents.

    There are several motivations for positing lexical inferences as part of event structure. First, event-related lexical inferences offer a standard for classification of event-denoting expressions. For instance, the event structure of creation verbs such as build, create, make, etc. includes subevents inferred lexically due to a particular lexical semantic property of the verbs: a change of existence from not_exist to exist. Consider the sentences in (1).

    image

    The creation verb build has two lexically inferred states, in addition to the process of building the house. The sentenceJohn has built the house presupposes the sentence in (1b) and entails the sentence in (1c). Consider the event structure of build according to the GL (Pustejovsky 1995; p. 82).

    image

    Based on the event structure in (2), we cannot exactly capture what changes from what to what, because it does not provide information about lexical inferences of build – specially, a lexically presupposed state. Every verb representing a change lexically presupposes a state before the change and entails a result state after that. The presupposed and entailed states provide a semantic clue for lexical semantic classification of verbs.

    Secondly, a semantic relation between verb pairs such as kill and die can only be understood by their inferential relations in the event structure of the verb kill. The verb kill lexically entails die. In addition, the lexical semantic difference between lead and follow depends on their lexical inferences related with their event structure. The verbs will be analyzed specifically in section 3.4. A proper lexical semantic theory must have an appropriate mechanism to represent information about lexical inferences related with the event structure of event-denoting expressions, because lexical inferences are crucial to clarify semantic properties of event-denoting expressions and give a criterion for lexical semantic classification of the expressions.

    The paper will proceed as follows; I introduce event structure and its components of the GL in section 2. In the following two sections, I describe various types of lexical inferences to support the proposal of this paper. Section 3 is about lexical entailments and section 4 about lexical presuppositions. In section 5, I propose a modified event structure. Section 6 is for conclusion and discussion of future research.

    2. Event Structure in the Generative Lexicon

    In the GL, event structure is a structured list of events with their types (aspectual classes), the ordering restriction over the events, and the property of headedness. Regarding event types, the GL assumes that subevents can be classified into at least three sorts: processes, states, and transitions. The event structure of process or state verbs is a simplex structure composed of only one subevent. When the event type of an event-denoting expression is a transition, its event structure is a complex structure with plural subevents.

    The ordering restriction over event structure represents temporal and mereological (part-of) relations between an event and its subevents. It can be one of the three kinds:

    Given that the event e3 is a complex event structure constituted of two subevents, e1 and e2, the relation of exhaustive ordered part of (<) states that e1 temporally precedes e2, each is a logical part of e3 and there is no other event that is part of e3 (See the event structure of build in (2)). RESTR represents the order restriction. The relation of exhaustive overlap part of (◯) expresses that e1 and e2 are completely simultaneous temporally as shown in (3).

    image

    The event structure of accompany, when it is interpreted as a motion verb, in (3) has two process subevents which happen simultaneously. The relation exhaustive ordered overlap (<◯) defines the event e1 containing two subevents e2 and e3, where e2 starts before e3 and overlaps. See an example of an exhaustive ordered overlap relation in (4).

    image

    Unlike accompany, the event structure of the verb follow presupposes John’s moving began slightly earlier than my moving to the conference room. Therefore, the restriction in this case is exhaustive ordered overlap.

    In addition, event structure of the GL has a way of representing the relative prominence of a subevent comparing with other subevents. The head is the most prominent subevent in the event structure of a predicate. For instance, the head is assigned to the process subevent e1 for accomplishment verbs such as build. On the other hand, the GL assumes that an achievement verb like arrive assigns the head to the result state (e2). See an example of achievement verbs in (5).

    image

    Based on the conceptual design of event structure described above, Pustejovsky (1995) presents twelve kinds of event structure types as shown in (6).

    image

    Distinction between accomplishment and achievement verbs depends on the headedness property of the verb classes (See 6a and 6b). (6c) illustrates events involving a subclass of ditransitive transfer verbs such as give and take. Verb pairs such as buy and sell are characterized by (6e) and (6f) respectively, where there are two simultaneous events involved in the transaction, but only one is focused by the lexical item (Pustejovsky 1995: p. 73). However, a relational predicate such as marry has the heads assigned on both subevents. Pustejovsky (1995) considers walk has an exhaustive ordered overlap restriction.1 Some verbs are underspecified with no head (6d, 6h, and 6l).

    Until now, I explained event structure of the GL in brief. Event structure needs to include lexical inferences of event-denoting expressions in order for it to capture better the lexical meaning of the expressions. In the next two sections, I show several types of lexical inferences. Section 3 treats lexical entailments based on event structure.

    1This analysis of the verb walk can be arguable. I do not discuss about it in detail here. I just consider walk to have the event structure composed of a process and a state which are simultaneous.

    3. Event-Related Lexical Entailments

    In this section, I explore various types of event structure-related lexical entailments. First, a result state is a subevent in the complex event structure of transition (change) verbs. The GL implies a lexical entailment relation between an event and its result state.2 I suggest to represent the entailment relation explicitly. Secondly, some motion verbs have a lexically entailed state – being on the path –, which is simultaneous to the other subevent with a process event type. Section 3.2 discusses this type of entailment. Thirdly, some causative verbs which belong to a process or an accomplishment aspectual class entail a process subevent. In section 3.3, I analyze the lexical entailment of those verbs.

       3.1 Result States as Lexical Entailment

    Most complex event structures consist of a process and a result state. See the event structure of the change-of-location verb arrive below.

    image

    In (7c), e1 represents the process of John’s arriving and e2 the result state that John is at school. The sentence in (7a) entails semantically the sentence in (7b) which denotes the result state e2, since the latter is always true when the former is true.3 That is, if John has arrived at school, John is necessarily at school as a result. The entailment is based on the event structure of the verb arrive. If the relation between then sentence in (7a) and that in (7b) is a presupposition, the latter sentence must be true under the negation of the former. See the sentences in (8).

    image

    The sentence John has not arrived at school (8a) does not entail the sentence John is at school (8b (=7b)),4 since when the sentence in (8a) is true, the sentence in (8b) is not true. If John has not arrived at school, John cannot be at school. Therefore, the sentence in (7a) does not presuppose the sentence in (7b (=8b)). Consider the conjunction of the two sentences in (9).

    image

    The conjunction of the two sentences in (9a) is semantically odd but that in (9b) is acceptable. The conjunction test shows that the sentence John has arrived at school entails but does not presuppose the sentence John is at school. The change-of-location verb arrive entails the result state of the arriving event – John’s being at school. This kind of entailment can be applied to all verbs denoting change.

       3.2 Other Lexically Entailed States

    In addition to change verbs that have a lexically entailed result state, there are other verb classes with a lexically entailed state in their event structure. Motion verbs such as walk and pass have a lexically entailed state simultaneous with a moving process. Since a moving event naturally presupposes a path of moving, it always entails the state in which a mover is on the path. Usually, the event type of a typical motion verb walk is thought of as a process, whose event structure is simple. But I argue that the event structure of walk is composed of a process subevent denoting a motion process and a state in which a mover is on the path, as presented in (10c).

    image

    The sentence which denotes John’s walking in (10a) entails the sentence in (10b), since if John walked slowly, then it is true that John was on the path of walking. In (10a), the walking path is not realized syntactically. But it is considered as a default argument, in terms of the GL, which is logically necessary for the verbs which denote motion events. The path of moving is syntactically realized in the following sentence in (11).

    image

    The prepositional phrase headed by along is a path argument of walk in the sentence of (11). John was on the street while John was walking along the street. Therefore, the sentence in (11a) entails the sentence in (11b). The entailment relation between the two sentences results from the lexical meaning of the motion verb walk.

    Another example is a change-of-location verb such as pass. The verb pass takes a path argument realized as a syntactic object.

    image
    image

    From the test of presupposition in (12) and (13), we conclude that the sentence John is passing the bridge entails but does not presuppose the sentence John is on the bridge.

    However, every change-of-location verb does not have a lexically entailed state mentioned above. For example, the verb transfer does not take an expression which denotes a path as its necessary argument, even though it is a change-of-location verb. It requires only source and goal arguments as its default arguments. See the sentence in (14).

    image

    The path of the patient’s moving is not exactly captured by the sentence in (14). The verb transfer is an achievement change-of-location verb which does not require a path argument as its necessary argument. For that kind of change-of-location verb, we cannot postulate the lexically entailed state of the agent’s being on the path when the event occurs. All achievement change-of-location verbs including arrive and leave belong to this group.

    To sum up, I argued that most motion verbs whose aspectual class is a process or an accomplishment have a lexically entailed state – being on the path of moving – which is simultaneous with the process of moving. However, motion verbs which belong to the achievement aspectual class do not entail the state – agent’s being on the path –, because a path argument is not necessary logically for them. Until now, I showed some verbs which entail a state subevent. However, some verbs entail a process subevent lexically. In the next section, I show the examples of verbs which have a lexically entailed process subevent in their event structure.

       3.3 Lexically Entailed Processes

    In this section, I show lexically entailed processes. First, causative motion verbs such as walk (causative) have a lexically entailed process as one of its subevents. The verb walk can be used as a causative motion verb as presented in (15).5

    image

    The sentence John is walking his dog entails his dog is walking but not presupposes it as the presupposition test in (15) shows it. Causative motion verbs such as lead and guide also belong to the group of verbs that have a lexically entailed process. The verb guide has two process subevents: a causer’s moving and a causee’s moving.

    image

    In (16), John’s guiding of me to the conference room entails moving of both John and me to the conference room.

    image

    The presupposition test in (17) shows that the verb guide does not necessarily presuppose that both John and I moved. Causative and interaction verbs such as walk and guide lexically entail a process subevent. In the next subsection, I show some examples of lexically entailed events – transitions.

       3.4 Lexically Entailed Transitions

    In the introduction, I pointed out that the semantic relation between kill and die is defined by their lexical inferential relation based on the event structure of the verb kill. Most causative verbs entail their corresponding unaccusative verbs. Consider the two sentences in (18).

    image

    If John killed Mary, she has died. But it is not true that she has died in the case that John did not kill Mary. Therefore, the verb kill entails the verb die lexically. Mary’s dying is a subevent in the event structure of the verb kill in the sentence of (18a). The event-related entailment relation is different from the ontological entailment relation such as hypernymy or synonymy. Compare the relation between kill and die in (18) with the semantic relation of kill and murder in (19).

    image

    Although the verb murder entails kill, the latter is a hypernym (or synonym) of the former. It is important that the entailment relation between kill and die is based on their event structural property, not the other semantic relations such as synonym or hypernym. The event structure-based lexical entailment relation should be encoded as a component of event structure, since it is a relation between the matrix event of killing and its subevent: dying.

    Another interesting example of a lexically entailed transition is the so-called interaction verbs such as lead and follow. Consider the sentences in (20).

    image

    If John lead me to the conference room, it is true that I followed John to the conference room. Therefore, the verb lead entails follow lexically. Most interaction verbs such as lead, follow, sell, etc. show this kind lexical entailment relation to their corresponding verbs.

    I point out that a specific analysis of the verb groups which have lexical entailments is not the aim of this paper. What I focus on here is the argument that event structure should represent the lexical entailments mentioned above. There can be many verb classes which entail various kinds of subevents lexically and we need to study which verb class has what kind of lexical entailments. I leave the issues for the future research. I turn to event-related lexical presuppositions in section 4.

    2Recent versions of the GL such as Pustejovsky and Moszkowicz (2008) imply more positively the lexically entailed states, as pointed out by a reviewer. A main focus of this paper is to represent lexical inferences including lexical presuppositions as well as lexical entailments explicitly in the event structure. Moreover, I think the types of inferential relations between an event and its proper subevents should be encoded as a component of event structure. Of course, many issues resulting from this change, including relations to other representation levels such as argument structure and qualia structure, must be studied carefully in the future.  3I define an entailment relation semantically, following the GL (Pustejovsky 1995: p. 24). An expression A semantically entails B if and only if every situation that makes A true, makes B true.  4I adopt the definition of semantic presupposition. A semantically presupposes B if and only if both (a) in all situations where A is true, B is true, and (b) in all situations where A is false, B is true (Pustejovsky 1995: p. 24).  5As a reviewer pointed out, examples of causative-unaccusative alternations of the kind ‘John walked’ vs. ‘John walked his dog’ or ‘john broke the vase’ vs. ‘The vase broke’ have been analyzed as instances of subevent foregrounding within the same event structure in a number of previous studies including the GL and Pustejovsky and Busa (1995). Nevertheless, the examples presented in this paper assume a separate event structure for each of them. In this paper, I take a neutral position and leave it for the future research since the main purpose of this paper is to show the motivations for introducing lexical inferences into event structure and propose a modified event structure.

    4. Event-related Lexical Presuppositions

    In this section, I explore two types of lexical presuppositions: processes and states. There are some previous studies that mention lexically presupposed processes. In section 4.1, I show a preparatory process for durative achievement verbs, suggested by Caudal (2005), as an example of a lexically presupposed process. Section 4.2 describes another type of lexically presupposed process that Engelberg (2006) observed. Finally, I introduce several kinds of lexically presupposed states in section 4.3.

       4.1 Preparatory Processes for Durative Achievement

    Verbs Caudal, in his research paper about the Stage Structure Theory (2005), suggests a preparatory stage as a lexical presupposition for a special kind of achievement verbs named durative achievement verbs.6 According to Caudal (2005), preparatory stages are causal stages instantiated for some types of atomic (so-called ‘punctual’) telic situations.7 It is a traditional point-of-view on achievement verbs that they do not have a durative process in their event structure. Consider the data from Martin (2010) and Caudal (2005) below.

    image

    Achievement verbs are incompatible with adverbs of completion such as partially and partly as shown in (21a). Moreover, they cannot co-occur with agentive adverbs like carefully. See the sentence in (21b). They cannot be embedded under aspectual verbs like stop or finish, because one cannot stop or finish a process which has not duration at all (See the sentences in (22)).

    image

    Nevertheless, achievement verbs such as win are perfectly compatible with the progressive, contrary to Vendler (1957)’s distinction between achievement and accomplishment. See an example in (23).

    image

    Several researchers argue that the kind of achievement verbs are in fact durative ones which presuppose a durative process that prepare for the culmination of the whole event (Caudal 1999, 2002; Kearns 2003; Engelberg 1999, 2000; etc.). I show an example below to help readers understand what a preparatory process is.

    image

    When the sentence in (24a) is true, the sentence in (24c) is true. The sentence John was reaching the summit remains true under the negation of the sentence in (24a). Therefore, the sentence in (24c), a preparatory stage for the culmination, is a presupposition of the sentence in (24a). The preparatory stages are selected under prospective readings of the past progressive. Caudal (2005) argues that the preparatory stage is peripheral to the stage structure and has a presuppositional status.8 Engelberg (2004, 2006) support the idea that a preparatory process is a lexical presupposition. I introduce another type of lexically presupposed process observed by Engelberg (2006) in the next subsection.

       4.2 Other Lexically Presupposed processes: Engelberg (2006)

    The lexically presupposed processes described in this section are different from the preparatory process (or stage) mentioned above, in that it is not a preparing process for culmination of the core event but just an independent presupposed process. Engelberg (2006) shows an example of the lexically presupposed process. Consider the German verb fangen ‘to catch’ in (25).

    image

    Both sentences in (25a) and (25b) entail the sentence in (25c). Therefore, the verb fangen ‘to catch,’ in the sense of ‘catch a flying object,’ presupposes the process ‘the ball’s flying.’ It does not indicate her activity of preparing to catch the ball. It is just a process in which the ball, an affected theme, was flying. The process ends when the catching event culminates. Thus, the ball is no longer flying as a result.

    According to Engelberg (2006), verbs of interaction like folgen ‘follow,’ antworten ‘answer,’ nachgeben ‘give in,’ and trotzen ‘defy’ are another instances with the kind of presupposed process. I show the LES9 of folgen ‘follow’ in (26). In the first subevent, a presupposed process, a participant (y) acts. The other participant (x) acts in the second subevent.

    image

    In this section, I showed examples of lexically presupposed processes observed by Engelberg (2006). I agree with Engelberg (2006) about the lexical presuppositions presented in this section. The next subsection turns to lexically presupposed states.

       4.3 Lexically Presupposed States

    I present another type of lexical presupposition – a lexically presupposed state in this section. All verbs denoting change are supposed to have a (or more) lexically presupposed state(s), since they have the meaning of change 9 The Lexical Event Structure (LES) is a structure which represents lexical semantic information in the lexical semantic theory, named the Lexical Event Structure Theory, developed by Engelberg (2004, 2006). from a state to another state. For example, the change-of-location verb reach has a lexically presupposed state. Consider the sentences in (27).

    image

    If the sentence in (27a) is true, the sentence in (27b) is also true, since it is impossible for John to be on the summit until John reaches the summit. When the sentence in (27c) is true, the sentence in (27b) is true, too. The test of presupposition shows the sentence in (27b) represents a lexically presupposed state subevent of the event denoted by the sentence in (27a). See a conjunction test for presupposition in (28).

    image

    The conjunction test in (28) shows the state of John’s not being on the summit is a presupposition of the event of John’s reaching on the summit.

    Another group of change-of-location verbs also presupposes a state before an event happens. The verb leave lexically presupposes the state of an agent’s being at the source location before the beginning of an event.

    image

    In (29a), the sentence John was in the library is true, when the sentence John has left the library is true. As shown in (29b), John’s being in the library remains true even under the negation of the sentence. It shows that the verb leave presupposes the state of John’s being in the library in the sentence John has left the library.

    Another motion verb pass, which belongs to an accomplishment verb class, also has its own lexical presupposition.

    image

    Before the passing event began, John was not on the bridge. If John was already on the bridge, John could not begin passing the bridge. Under the negation of the sentence in (30b), the sentence John was not on the bridge is true. The presupposition test in (30) shows that pass presupposes the state that a mover is not on the path.

    Until now, I explored the lexically presupposed states of change-oflocation verbs. I apply the idea of a lexically presupposed state to all change verbs with complex event structure such as change-of-state and change-ofpossession verb classes. Creation verbs such as build represent the change of existence from non-existence to existence. That is to say, something which has not existed becomes to exist by the creation event.

    image

    Since the sentence in (31c) is true if the sentence in (31a) is true, the former entails the latter – a resultant state of the building event. The sentence in (31b) is a presupposition of the sentence (31a). See the sentences in (32)

    image

    Because both (32a) and (32b) entail (32c), the sentence (32c) is a presupposition of the sentence (32a). The presupposition relation results from the lexical semantic property of the creation verb build.

    Since a change-of-possession verb represents that a theme moves from its possessor to another person, the event denoted by a verb in the class presupposes that someone possessed a theme before the change of possession. I show an example of the typical change-of-possession verb give below.

    image

    The change-of-possession verb give lexically presupposes two states, which are linked to a giver and a receiver, respectively. The sentences in (33b) and (33c) show the presuppositions. First, the sentence John has given the book to Mary presupposes that John had the book before the giving event occurred.

    image

    Under the negation of the sentence (33a), the sentence John had the book is still true, as shown in (34). Therefore, the sentence (33a) presupposesJohn had the book (33b). Likewise, give presupposes the state in which Mary didn’t have the book before the event happened.10

    Until now, I described various kinds of lexical inferences of verbs related with their event structur 11 . Based on the observation, I suggest a modified version of event structure in which lexical inferences are encoded.

    6See Caudal (1999) for a full account of durative achievement verbs. I doubt if the preparatory process for the durative achievement verbs is a necessary subevent in the event structure of the verbs. The issue may be related with various questions:what is defined as a presupposition?; what kind of information should be included in the event structure of a lexical item?; how different is lexical semantics from lexical pragmatics?; etc. I leave the issue for the future research. I just cite Caudal (2005) and Engelberg (2006) in order to motivate the incorporation of various kinds of lexical presuppositions into event structure.  7Caudal does use the terms stage and situation instead of subevent and event, respectively in his Stage Structure theory (Caudal 2005).  8This issue is closely related with his idea about salience. I leave it for the future research.  9The Lexical Event Structure (LES) is a structure which represents lexical semantic information in the lexical semantic theory, named the Lexical Event Structure Theory, developed by Engelberg (2004, 2006).  10Assuming it is impossible that both John and Mary have the book at the same time, the two presuppositions might be complementary and thus representing both in the event structure of give may be logically redundant. However, the assertion is arguable since there are many things people can share. For instance, informationlike things can be shared by many people at the same time. Even though a person give an information to another person, (s)he still has the information. I do not delve into the issue here.  11There are restitutive verbs with the prefix re- which presuppose the occurrence of an event. Since the analysis of the verbs is not so simple, I will prepare a research paper for the verbs in the future. Refer to Marantz (2007) and Wunderlich (2001) for the morpho-syntactic and semantic approaches. In addition, the research papers about the adverb again and its presupposition (Pederson 2014; Dobler 2008a, 2008b) will give some insight to the study of restitutive verbs.

    5. Modified Event Structure

    In section 5.1, I discuss why lexical inferences should be represented in the event structure. I reconsider how to partition an event in section 5.2. Section 5.3 discusses how to incorporate event-related lexical inferences into event structure in the GL and what should be changed as a result of the incorporation, focusing on the mereological treatment of event structure, ordering restriction, and headedness. In the last section, I show the modified event structure frame as a summary.

       5.1 Why do Lexical Inferences have to be encoded in Event Structure?

    Why do the lexical inferences need to be incorporated into event structure? All kinds of lexical inferences are not necessarily related with event structure. Compare the verbs build and construct in (35).

    image

    The two sentences in (35) have a mutual entailment relation between each other. However, the entailment relation does not rely on the event structure of build and construct. The verb build is a synonym of construct. The inferences based on an ontological relation are not subevents represented in the event structure of build or construct.

    On the contrary to the lexical inference mentioned above, the eventrelated lexical inferences are only derived by a subeventual analysis of the event denoted by a verb. For instance, I analyze the inferences of the sentence in (36a).

    image

    The sentence in (36a) presupposes the sentence in (36b) and entails the sentence in (36c). Both the presupposition and the entailment are based on the event structure of the creation verb build. The inferences in (36b) and (36c) cannot be recognized without a subeventual analysis of the verb build. Therefore, information about event-related lexical inferences should be encoded in the event structure. In the next section, I discuss about the partition of an event.

       5.2 Partition of an Event

    The event denoted by an expression, if it has a complex event structure, is usually decomposed to two subevents: e1 (process) and e2 (result state). The achievement verb arrive has a bipartite event structure with two subevents, as presented in (37).

    image

    However, I showed that there are more than two subevents in the event structure of verbs of change. Event structure does not need to be a bipartite structure. I define event structure as a structured list of event parameters, following the GL. Nevertheless, event structure can be roughly considered to have three semantic parts below.

    Although the number of subevents is not restricted quantitatively, pragmatic inferences cannot be encoded in the event structure. Lexical inferences should be distinguished from pragmatic (contextual) inferences and event structure has to include only lexical inferences. Nishiyama & Koenig, in their paper about a perfect state (2004), separated the lexical entailment (38a) from the conversational implicature (38b) for the sentence Ken has broken his leg, as presented in (39).

    image
    image

    According to them, the state that Ken’s leg is broken (38a) is a subevent in the event structure of break in (38) but the state that Ken is behind in his work (38b) is excluded. The principle that only lexical inferences are to be subevents restricts the number of subevents.

    In addition, I reject the approach that treats a culmination as a separate subevent and postulates a tripartite event structure (Moens & Steedman 1988, Kamp & Reyle 1993, and the VerbNet group (Dang et. Al. 2000, Kipper et. Al. 2000)). Consider the event structure of the verb build analyzed by Moens & Steedman (1988) in (40).

    image

    According to the diagram in (40), the event structure of build is composed of three subevents: a preparatory process (they build), a culmination (they complete the bridge), and a consequent state (they have completed the bridge). A culmination is an event which the speaker views as punctual or instantaneous, and as accompanied by a transition to a new state of the world. This new state is referred to as the consequent state of the event. A preparatory process means any process before the culmination of an event. Patrick Caudal, in his paper about stage structure (2005), criticizes the tripartite structure approach, arguing that a culmination is merely the endpoint of the first stage, that is, a process. I adopt Caudal (2005)’s point- of-view.

       5.3 Relations between an event and its subevents

    In section 5.3, I explore the relational properties of components of the modified event structure. Event structure in the GL has mereological (part-of) relation, order restriction, and headedness as its relational properties. In 5.3.1, I suggest to withdraw the mereological treatment of event structure.

    5.3.1 Mereological Treatment of Event Structure

    The original approach to event structure in the GL adopts the mereological treatment of the relation between an event and its subevents. That is, all subevents are exhaustive parts of an event. However, researchers such as Caudal criticize the mereological analysis of event structure.12 I do not delve into Caudal’s argument about the part-of relation. But we need to think about what is the range of an event. For that purpose, let us consider the embedding of the event-denoting expressions under the aspectual verbs such as begin and finish.

    image

    Under the aspectual verbs begin and finish, the event of building the house only includes the process of building the house. Specifically, a result state is usually included in the event structure as a part of an event but it is not exactly a part of the event as we recognize from the test of the aspectual verb finish or end. Rather, it is an entailed (or caused) state. Event-related lexical presuppositions also are temporally before the beginning of an event. Nevertheless, lexical semantic approaches interested in lexical aspectual analysis of event-denoting verbs assume the subeventual analysis with event structure-like frames as a part of their lexical semantic representation system. It is because the subeventual analysis gives a big help to explain many linguistic phenomena such as selection restriction, argument alternation, and lexical inferences. I withdraw the mereological treatment of the event structure.13 Instead, I suggest to add inferential relations between an event and its subevents into event structure as its component.

    I point out that my analysis is slightly different from Pustejovsky (2000) regarding the temporal ordering relation between an event and its lexically presupposed subevents. Pustejovsky (2000) only considers the time interval in which an event occurs. However, I assume that its lexically presupposed subevent is already in progress when an event begins, considering the time interval before the occurrence of an event.14 The lexically presupposed subevent does not need to terminate necessarily when an event begins.

    5.3.2 Semantic Relation between Presupposition and Entailment

    Superficially, the relation between presupposed states and entailed result states based on event structure might seem to be just a logical negation relation. Consider the lexical presupposition and the lexical entailment of the verb build presented in (42).

    image

    It is true that the presupposition in (42b) is a logical negation of the entailment in (42c). However, the semantics of opposition (Pustejovsky, 2000) for change verbs provides the grounds of the argument that the opposition relation between the presupposed state and the entailed result state is not simply a logical relation. The logical negation is derived from the lexical semantic property related with subeventual analysis of change verbs. Pustejovsky (2000) proposes the Event Persistence Structure (EPS) and defines it as in (43), so that it can represent “contradictions of change”.

    image

    Pustejovsky (2000) argues that the effect of the activity of fixing the faucets will render the description leaky applied to each faucet as contradictory in (44a); similarly, in (44b), the felicity of the description powdered applied to the milk is true only before the completion of the event of mixing and not after.

    image

    A finer model of change is needed within semantic theory to handle such phenomena. Furthermore, this model must incorporate the properties of persistence over the event as well as change.

    There are two kinds of opposition structure: binary opposition and polar opposition. When there are only a term and its opposition and there is no middle term between them, the opposition structure is a binary opposition. In that case, if the negation of a term has its lexical form, it also is a binary opposition. On the other hand, if there are middle terms between two polar terms, the opposition is a polar opposition. I show examples of opposition structure in (45).

    image

    The opposition relation between presuppositions and entailments is not simply a logical negation in the modified event structure. Rather, the relation reflects the crucial lexical semantic property of change verbs. In the next subsection, I mention the temporal ordering restriction and headedness.

    5.3.3 Temporal Ordering Restriction and Headedness

    The temporal ordering restriction in the GL is still important to define the relations among subevents in the modified event structure. I adopt the three temporal ordering relations in the GL: precedence (<), overlap (◯), and ordered overlap (<◯). Consider the following examples.

    image

    In (46), the causative verb walk entails the subevents se1, se2, and se3, which happen simultaneously. Therefore, the temporal ordering restriction between them is overlap. Now, let us consider the temporal ordering relations between subevents for change verbs with complex event structure.

    image

    The change-of-location verb arrive has three subevents as shown in (47). The subevent se1 is a lexically presupposed state and se2 is a process. The last subevent se3 is a lexical entailment, which is a result state. When the state se1 began is unknown but the state remains until the arriving ends. Therefore, the subevent se1 overlaps another subevent se2. On the other hand, se2 precedes se3.15 Contrastively, the temporal ordering between subevents of the verb leave is as shown in (48).

    image

    I keep a temporal ordering restriction as a component of the modified event structure.

    Because the modified event structure I propose here is roughly composed of three parts, headedness also may be more complicated than that in the GL. I have some questions about headedness. First, is the headedness a necessary component of the modified event structure? Second, what would be the role of headedness? What would be the relation between headedness and Caudal (2005)’s salience? Caudal (2005) argues that the headedness cannot account for the salience relation of subevents. Comparing between headedness and salience will give an insight to research on headedness in the modified event structure.

       5.4 A Modified Event Structure Frame

    I proposed that event structure should include lexical inferential relations between an event and its subevents. In order to support the proposal, I presented many types of lexical presuppositions and entailments which are related with the event structure of verbs. In addition, I suggested to withdraw the mereological treatment of event structure. Although the event structure need not to be a bipartite structure, it should include only event-related lexical inferences and exclude the other inferences. For now, temporal ordering restrictions between subevents and headedness remain as components of the event structure. Considering what I mentioned, I show the modified event structure frame below.

    image

    The subscripted Prepresents a presupposition and the subscripted E means an entailment. The inferential relations between an event and its proper subevents are encoded by INFERENCE in the modified event structure. I show the modified event structure of the verb arrive as an example in (50).

    image

    The event structure of arrive in (50) is a modified version of event structure. The three subevents include a lexically presupposed state, a core process of arriving, and the lexically entailed state (a result state). EID means the id of the matrix event John’s arriving in Seoul. SUBEVENTS represents a list of subevents. INFERENCE expresses the lexical inferential relations between the matrix event and its subevents. RESTR represents the temporal ordering relations between subevents. HEAD represents headedness.

    12Caudal (2005)’s critic point is that the mereological treatment of event structure cannot account for the salience.  13A reviewer pointed out that the examples with aspectual verbs such as begin and finish do not necessarily prove that the event of building only includes the process. But I think if subevents are temporally parts of a matrix event, the test with aspectual verbs is appropriate. A problem is what kind of criterion should be applied to decide the boundary of an event. This will be one of the future research topics. I will study more research including Piñón’s work on mereological treatment of event structure.  14The beginning time of a lexically presupposed subevent is usually unknown.  15Since the end point of the arriving is the beginning point of the result state, the temporal restriction might be an ordered overlap (<◯).

    6. Conclusion

    The aim of this paper was to propose that lexical inferences be incorporated into event structure. In order to support the proposal, I described various kinds of lexical inferences including entailment and presupposition.

    Incorporating lexical inferences into event structure results in various changes regarding event structure in the GL. First, an event does not have a part-of relation to its subevents. Rather, the relation between the two is defined as an inferential relation. Secondly, event structure can have as many subevents as possible but the subevents must be event-related lexical inferences, not contextual implicatures. In addition, event structure roughly consists of lexical presuppositions, a core process, and lexical entailment. Thirdly, a temporal ordering restriction can be more complicated than that of the GL because it must show temporal relations between all subevents. Fourthly, headedness also becomes more complicated or it might be changed (or removed). These issues remain for the future research. As well, classification of lexical inferences depending on different verb classes is one of interesting future works.

    In spite of many issues not solved yet, I think this research will give some challenge to event structure theory, specially the GL. Furthermore, this work is very useful for textual inferences tasks in computational linguistics, as shown already in Im (2013). Stede (1996) also includes pre-state, activity, and post-state in the event structure of a transition event.

참고문헌
  • 1. Caudal P. 1999 Achievements vs. Accomplishments: A Computational Treatment of Atomicity, Incrementality, and Perhaps of Event Structure. [Proceedings of Taln99] google
  • 2. Caudal P. 2002 Stage Structure and Stage Salience for Event Semantics [paper presented to the Workshop on the Syntax and Acquisition of Aspect.] google
  • 3. Caudal P. 2005 Stage Structure and Stage Salience for Event Semantics. Aspectual Inquiries. P.239-264 google
  • 4. Dang H., Kipper K., Palmer M. 2000 Integrating compositional semantics into a verb lexicon. [Proceedings of the 18 th conference on Computational linguistics-Volume 2.] google
  • 5. Dobler E. 2008a ‘Again’ and the Structure of Result States. [Proceedings of ConSOLE XV] P.41-66 google
  • 6. Dobler E. 2008b Creating as Putting Something into the World. [Proceedings of ConSOLE XVI] P.39-50 google
  • 7. Engelberg S. 1999 The Magic of the Moment ? What it Means to be a Punctual Verb. S. Chang, L. Liaw, J. Ruppenhofer (eds.) [Proceedings of the 25 th Annual Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistic Society] P.109-121 google
  • 8. Engelberg S. 2000 Verb Meaning as Event Structure. A. Lommel & A. Melby (eds.) [Proceedings of the 26 th LACUS Forum, Edmonton] P.257-268 google
  • 9. Engelberg S. 2004 Lexical Event Structures for Verb Semantics. [Journal of Language and Linguistics] Vol.3 P.62-108 google
  • 10. Engelberg S. 2006 A Theory of Lexical Event Structures and Its Cognitive Motivation. [Advances in the Theory of the Lexicon] Vol.13 P.235 google
  • 11. Im Seohyun, Advisor ? Pustejovsky J. 2013 The Generator of the Event Structure Lexicon (GESL): Automatic Annotation of Event Structure for Textual Inference Tasks. google
  • 12. Im Seohyun, Pustejovsky J. 2009 Annotating Event Implicatures for Textual Inference Tasks. [Proceedings of the 5 th International Conference on Generative Approaches to the Lexicon] google
  • 13. Im Seohyun, Pustejovsky J. 2010 Annotating Lexically Entailed Subevents for Textual Inference Tasks. [FLAIRS Conference 2010] google
  • 14. Kearns K. 2003 Durative Achievements and Individual-Level Predicates on Events. [Linguistics and Philosophy] Vol.26 P.595-636 google cross ref
  • 15. Kipper K., Dang H. T., Palmer M. 2000 Class-Based Construction of a Verb Lexicon. [AAAI-00 Proceedings] google
  • 16. Martin F. 2010 Revisiting the Distinction between Accomplishment and Achievements. google
  • 17. Marantz A. 2007 Restitutive ‘re-’ and the First Phases Syntax/Semantics of the VP. Paper given at the University of Maryland. google
  • 18. Moens M., Steedman M. 1988 Temporal Ontology and Temporal Reference. [Computational Linguistics] Vol.14 P.15-38 google
  • 19. Nishiyama A., Koenig J. P. 2004 What is a perfect state? WCCFL 23 Proceedings. (ed.) B. Schmeiser, V. Chand, A. Kelleher and A. Rodriguez P.101-113 google
  • 20. Pederson W. A. 2014 A Scalar Analysis of ‘Again’-Ambiguities. [Journal of Semantics] google
  • 21. Pustejovsky J. 1995 The Generative Lexicon. google
  • 22. Pustejovsky J. 2000 Events and the Semantics of Opposition. Events as Grammatical Objects P.445-482 google
  • 23. Pustejovsky J., Busa F. 1995 Unaccusativity and Event Composition. In P. M. Bertinetto, V. Binachi, J. Higginbotham, and M. Squartini (eds.) Temporal Reference: Aspect and Actionality. google
  • 24. Pustejovsky J., Moszkowicz J. L. 2008 Integrating Motion Predicate Classes with Spatial and Temporal Annotations. [In COLING 2008: Companion volume - Posters and Demonstrations] P.95-98 google
  • 25. Stede M. 1996 A Generative Perspective on Verbs and Their Readings. [Proceedings of the Eighth International Workshop on Natural Language Generation] google
  • 26. Vendler Z. 1957 Verbs and Times. [Philosophical Review] Vol.66 P.143-160 google cross ref
  • 27. Wunderlich D. 2001 Prelexical Syntax and the Voice Hypothesis. Audiatur Vox Sapientiae. P.487-513 google
OAK XML 통계
이미지 / 테이블
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
  • [ ] 
(우)06579 서울시 서초구 반포대로 201(반포동)
Tel. 02-537-6389 | Fax. 02-590-0571 | 문의 : oak2014@korea.kr
Copyright(c) National Library of Korea. All rights reserved.